| |
30.1 Rational theology
One traditional approach to metaphysics in rational theology is to define God
as “that than which no greater being can be conceived". Although this definition
may or may not yield Anselm’s proof for the existence of God,
it can certainly be used to determine the attributes that should be ascribed to
God. In careful hands, Ward (1996), for example, shows
how to, from this starting point, derive a theology in good agreement with our scientific
theism. The need for careful hands arises because of the difficulty in this method.
How do you decide which attributes are ‘greater’ than certain other attributes?
Is it greater to be unable to suffer or to be able to suffer? Aquinas thought that
God could not suffer (that God is impassible), whereas Whitehead (with many since
him) holds to the contrary that it is better that God suffers with the suffering
of his creatures.30.1Swedenborg
holds the intermediate position that God does not suffer but may at most grieve.
These three views follow directly from their respective ontologies: the God of Aquinas
is Pure Act; the God of Whitehead is within a process ontology; and the God of Swedenborg
is Love Itself. In our scientific theism, since God is characterized by being life
itself, he is certainly not unable to change, and hence he is not Pure Act because
he can respond to our love.
The theism and science presented in the previous sections attempt to explain
the relation between God and the world in a way that is rationally comprehensible.
The scheme must be devoid of self-contradiction or inconsistency, as otherwise anything
whatsoever could be proved. A reductio ad absurdam, for example, could
then be used to disprove any additional hypothesis. We acknowledge, of course, that
it is God we are here talking about, so we freely admit that there are infinite
depths and heights to God that we may take an eternity to try to understand. But
we insist that the further existence of these depths and heights does not
contradict our best rational understanding. We insist on this, in part, because
our best rationality comes from God (who is Wisdom itself) precisely for that purpose.
In requiring some rational comprehension to be faithfully true,30.2
scientific theism cannot include any kind of non-rational assertion that verges
on the self-contradictory. We cannot follow Plotinus, for example, in declaring
God to be beyond both being and non-being. Nor can we include the assertion of Aquinas
that in God essence and existence are identical, nor similarly that his substance
and form are identical. Nor do I see a non-contradictory manner for asserting that
God consists of three persons and yet is Absolutely Simple. Nor do I follow Aquinas
in saying that love and wisdom are not truly predicated of God except by analogy.
Perhaps some theologians feel free to add in such non-rational assertions as
addenda, but, unless it can be shown how such declarations may be consistent,
they cannot be part of any rational theism.
Part of the impetus for these assertions by Plotinus, Aquinas, and others is
their belief that God is greater when his unity is beyond not only all division
but also beyond all rational distinctions. To have to distinguish between
being and nonbeing or between essence and existence was ‘beneath’ God, they thought.
I reply that, while we may agree that God is “that than which no greater being
can be conceived", we are definitely not claiming that God is “greater
than can be conceived". It would clearly diminish God if these inflated unities
necessarily involved contradictions!30.3
|