| |
2.4 Insights and critiques
Instead of following or inventing a rational system of metaphysics, David Hume
(1711-1776) was more skeptical and wanted to ground his beliefs
only on what could be empirically observed. He attempted to form an entirely naturalistic
‘science of man’ that described the psychology of human nature. He saw this nature
as based on desires rather than on reasons, in contrast to the rationalists of the
previous generation. He was skeptical of religion, especially its more metaphysical
assertions and its acceptance of miracles. He wanted, with John Locke, to keep religion
separate from civic activities.
Emanuel Swedenborg (1688-1772) started out similarly following
the new scientific philosophies and wanted to understand how all of nature, organisms
and even the soul functioned in the world. To this end he began to develop theories
based on the observations of his contemporaries. However, in midlife he experienced
a kind of spiritual awakening that led, he said, to his constant presence in a spiritual
world as well as in the physical world. He then published many works detailing a
religious and theistic philosophy, from which I have learned a great deal. In fact,
I find in Swedenborg (1912) the clearest presentation
of the arguments within theism that I use in Part III,
in particular the arguments from love and from life, and also the universal three-fold
subdivision of parts. It continues to surprise me that his theories are not more
widely known. One reason for this may be that his philosophy was bound up with specifically
religious content which made historical and particular claims. His views were also
expressed in the terms of the science of his day that we know is no longer adequate.
Furthermore, his supporting evidence consisted of his spiritual explorations which
are difficult or impossible to replicate, though some reports of near-death experiences
show a commonality. Perhaps there will need to be further independent support for
Swedenborg’s claims before they can be generally accepted today.
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was a philosopher who was of two
minds about Swedenborg. Kant had also started out thinking about physics and nature,
being an enthusiastic supporter of the new sciences from Newton. Kant (1929)
tried to develop science along these lines, with several attempts to form realistic
ideas of space, forces and motion in nature. He wanted to include religion (or at
least the good effects that it has on practical reason for society), but, in the
new scientific age, he was unable to find a realistic basis for this in ontology
or metaphysics. He saw that Swedenborg claimed to have precisely what he needed
here--an empirical basis for a spiritual reality--but was unable to go along with
him for fear of disapproval by his academic peers. The product of this conflict
in 1766 was the anonymous2.6
book of Kant (2002), where he more-or-less accurately
describes Swedenborg’s theory but in the end ridicules Swedenborg and his claims.
In private he was more accepting. Palmquist (2002)
and Thorpe (2011) both explain how Kant’s later
philosophy of an ‘intelligible world’ can be usefully regarded as an attempt to
construct a view that has the same practical effect as would follow from
Swedenborg’s religious philosophy but with neither the ontological commitment nor
the allowance of any evidence not based on sensory inputs. In, for example, his
metaphysics lectures of 1782-3, given between the publication of the first and second
editions of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant argues for ideas rather similar
to those of Swedenborg. Kant argues in favor of the concept of a moral community
not governed by physical separations but by qualitative moral relations. Thorpe
points out a significant difference, however, in that Kant later arrives at a position
where that community in the intelligible world is determined by the free choices
of autonomous agents and hence not influenced by God. Such autonomous existences,
we note, are not really possible within theism.
|